Friday, October 31, 2008
EU Membership: Contradictory or Integral to the British Constitution?
With such a confidence, it seems contradictory that the United Kingdom conceded to join the European Union in 1972, an institution with guidelines that could potentially undermine the authority of the British constitution. This is a contradiction still debated within today’s society. In Postwar: A History of Europe Since 1945, Tony Judt states that the Prime Minister responsible for the United Kingdom’s participation was the “…only political leader since World War Two unambiguously and enthusiastically in favor of joining his nation’s fate to that of its continental neighbors” (Judt 526). Wright echoes this lack of country-wide sentiment, commenting that several citizens felt shortchanged and ignorant in the 1975 referendum (Wright 25). As the European Union has attempted to become even more closely unified, Britain has attempted to find its balance between receiving the benefits of the European Union while asserting a certain independence. Judt explains that their resistance to the common currency “…represented a device for blocking institutional integration” (Judt 716). Overall, in a continual attempt to define its identity, Britain has worked to reconcile its trust in its own independent political system that is continually shifting with other elements of identity, including class, race, and now a collective European identity (Wright 47). While the United Kingdom’s membership to the European Union might be interpreted as a challenge to its unique constitutional set-up, however, I agree with Wright’s claim that EU membership is not a challenge, but rather a part of the constitution, which is ultimately a narrative of the political shifts within the United Kingdom. Alongside the new issues facing nations today, the British constitution, anchored in tradition, will continue to document Britain’s interaction in the continually evolving history of man.
Thursday, October 30, 2008
British Politics: Recognizable yet on the Move…
Within British Politics, Tony Wright points out that Britain’s uniqueness stems from its distinctive geography, the absence of invasions since the 11th century Norman conquests and a lack of modern revolution, among other factors. In fact, while Britain certainly has an established system of governance, it lacks one uniform, codified document to which it can point as “the constitution” so that all of the documents that form its constitution are products of its history. However, having a strong, centralized and concentrated power of government and a single line of authority and accountability is not without its weaknesses. As Wright points out, the paradox of British politics is a strong governing capacity in combination with a weak administrative body. Thus, one might say that while the United States has a greater ineffectiveness in breaking down and moving past congressional deadlock, the political system of governance in Britain has its own source of ineffectiveness, namely, a weak system of mechanisms for translating policy into practice. Another interesting concept that Wright points out has to do with the way in which the British political system puts a primacy on governing. In other words, the British system of politics looks upon and understands the acquisition and exercise of power in a fundamentally different way than that of the United States, for a simple example. We think of power primarily in terms of limitation; the British think of power in terms of governing.
With the process of devolution in Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland, Tony Blair’s attempts to reform The House of Lords, and the argument for further integration of Britain into the European Union, the British system of government is certainly beginning to lose some of its idiosyncrasies. These changes present many implications. I will point out one of these as an example. In regards to the concept of responsible government, the traditional idea of ministerial accountability to Parliament no longer holds so that reforms of The House of Lords are likely to be followed by further reforms that may implement a more complex system of accountability checks on what can be seen as a rather lop-sided government. Certainly, it seems that Britain is treading a path of transformation, and it will be interesting to see what effects these reforms will have on the British system of politics as a whole.
1 http://www.epolitix.com/latestnews/article-detail/newsarticle/gordon-brown-leadership-acceptance-speech-in-full/
Britain's Balance of Power
Observers of British politics have often noted an apparent lack of balance of power in the British government, particularly when compared to the
An important question arises from the contrast between Americans’ and Britons' approach to balance of power.
Post-National Europe versus the rise of nationalism in the United States of America
British Politics
However, what Tony Wright does not discuss in great detail is the existence of opposition political parties as a potential check on the ruling government. True, the opposition parties have little ability to thwart legislation proposed by the government. However, this is not important. It is the threat that the opposition party provides that can keep the ruling party in line. In British Politics, the opposition party has essentially a shadow government, whose purpose it is to study the actions of the ruling party, so that if they should win the next election they are prepared to govern immediately. There is always a chance that the general population could become dissatisfied and vote the new party into power. In theory, this threat should prevent the ruling party from moving to far in a certain direction. However, this theory has not been proven to work in practice. Tony Wright himself points out the three political revolutions in Britain after World War II. These revolutions were the Attlee revolution, the Thatcher revolution, and the Blair revolution. In each of these revolutions, the governing parties sought to undue or change much of what the previous parties had enacted. While political parties and election are clearly a weak check on the ruling party, they do serve to prevent the governing party from getting out of control. Maybe a a lack of strong checks and balances is the reason that the British government has remained stable for so long. Revolutions are able to occur in a civilized political realm rather than on the battle field.
Thursday, October 23, 2008
Was the Moral Price paid worth it?
Judt explains in his work, Postwar, that post-war stability in Europe was largely based on the horrific actions of Hitler and Stalin, as well as the population transfer and ethnic cleansing of minorities, brought about by Europeans during and directly after the war because the outcome of these actions was, as Judt puts it, a “tidier” and more homogenous Europe. Even though the moral price paid by Europeans, both in condemnable actions and then disregard of these actions, brought much needed stability to the continent, it is difficult to argue that it was the right thing for Europe to do and that it created a better Europe in the end. The most apparent negative outcome of the new, “tidier”
Of course, there is essentially nothing Europeans could have done to stop Hitler and Stalin’s extermination, but the acts of ethnic cleansing and forced population transfers that took place after the war could have been avoided and stability still be ensured. Additionally, Europeans could have acknowledged the horrific crimes that Hitler committed against the Jews without threatening stability. Fortunately, Europeans eventually began to acknowledge their condemnable actions, but to think if things had occurred differently during and directly after the war, I am certain Europe would be a different place today, whether it would be better or worse I cannot say, but it is likely that they would be less fearful of diversity and more accepting of others because they would realize that it was intolerance and the non-acceptance of others as humans having worth that enabled the crimes against humanity to be committed during and after World War II.
Postwar, framework
Specifically, his piece is tainted by its Western centrism and teleological framework. Granted it is a history of Europe; however, he brushes over worldwide forces that shaped the history of the latter half of the twentieth century—forces, such as the loss of global European influence and dominance that inevitably impacted the new European identity of which he writes. As such, he falls into the same pattern of Western centrism that has largely discredited other historical works.
Furthermore, he claims to disregard previous writings and histories of Europe as they were obscured by the policies of the Cold War; yet, in the next breath he establishes an entirely new, yet now, obviously fictitious endpoint. He simply attempts to establish historical trends that led to the European situation in 1989, as opposed to the European situation in 1988.
Finally, as has been discussed in other posts, Judt oversteps his historical bounds into the world of political theorization in making the claim that the nation-state should no longer be the primary unit of analysis, based on the rise of the European Union. However, in light of the weakened status of Europe and the rising dominance of other nations, it is illogical to rest one’s thesis with regards to global politics on one region.
Judt’s claims are thus questionable if not contradictory and in no way an attempt to truly rectify historical analysis of post-war Europe.
Postwar
European Integration - a new unit of political study
Indeed, the first move toward a European Union began in the mid-1950s, with the formation of the European Steel and Coal Community. That this was seen as largely a way to avoid future conflict and integrate Germany into Europe speaks volumes about the way that economic mechanisms are intertwined with politics itself. The evolution of the European Union, as a successor to the European Economic Community, was itself just an outgrowth on the theme of integration. The fall of the Soviet Union and the need to rehabilitate ex-Soviet satellite states into the European community was a powerful and difficult issue, but its resolution into the 25 state European Union has proved to one of the most essential defining characteristics of the 21st century. Today, the European Union faces new crises, chief among them is how to expand or conserve the traditional definition of what it means to be a European – thus, we see an ongoing, and, some would say, irresolvable, issue of potential membership for Turkey in the EU. Furthermore, the home of the EU – Belgium – is undergoing its own European
All of this is instrumentally fundamental to our study of comparative politics. If we look at Europe as the birthplace and chief exporter of the modern nation-state, and if we see the state as the primary unit of measurement in sizing up the world, the integration of the various states of Europe into a single, cohesive unit poses new questions about ethnic, political, and social organization. These issues can be seen as just a by-product of the greater trends of globalization. But in the European sense, the European Union offers a new face of political life. We have studied extensively the different way states can look based on their economic and political makeup. In the case of the EU, we have a multitude of different types of people coming together to form something, which, although not a state, is stable and united.
Judt says that the European Union now is “coming to resemble Switzerland” (735). Despite the failure to ratify the Constitution of the EU, we can that this description says a lot about what has happened in Europe over the past 60 years. How have so many different states, with different political histories, different languages, different cultures, managed to come together like this? We have studied extensively the way in which different communities find their role in a state – think of the special status, and continuing conflict, of the province of Quebec for instance. The European community has somehow managed to emphasize its similarities and common goals over its differences. Underwriting all of this is something that Judt calls “the European way of life” – arguably analogous to Huntington’s description of a civilization. Whether such commitment to peace and stability can continue throughout the challenges of the 21st century – an influx of non-European immigrants, the question of Turkey, the lack of political constitution – is, of course, not certain. But the creation and success of the European federation thus far adds a whole new element to study of comparative politics.
“Europe as a way of life”
Judt in his book “Postwar: A History of Europe Since 1945” beautifully describes Europe’s struggle to recovery from the events of the beginning of the 20th century. Judt points out multiple ways that Europe began the road to stabilization. I think that his idea that Europe had to look to itself for the first time was very interesting. Throughout history Europe has been the hegemonic power in the international stage. It never really had to worry about its domestic issues, but more about states outside Europe. Judt points out that in order for Europe to recover after World War One and Two it had to join together and rebuild a foundation without its past. No longer did Europe have goals of conquering other nations or building stronger economies, but it had to work on rebuilding itself.
I thought it was important to recognize that in the past Europe was not always viewed as Europe, but rather as different state powers with different ideals and types of leadership. However after the wars, Europe had no option but to begin its model after the United States, literally a “united Europe”. I thought it was quite important how Judt pointed out that in order for Europe to survive it not only had to unite, but that each country within Europe had to develop of sense of allegiance to that state without losing its primary allegiance to Europe. This is very reminiscent of the U.S. Moreover, Judt points out that the only way of uniting and fixing Europe was to keep silent about much of its past. I think this is unfortunate but true in the sense that if European nations looked at how Germany killed their economies during World War Two, they would not have wanted to unite with Germany, therefore ruining the idea of “Europe as a way of life”.
Wednesday, October 22, 2008
From a Common Market to a Common Political Culture?
One of the most defining of the five main themes Tony Judt identifies in his introduction to Postwar: A History of
Despite the current problem of legitimacy facing the EU (stemming from issues ranging from excessive enlargement to that of the “democratic deficit”), as well as that of forging a consensus on how to reform the Union, perhaps the mere condition of being forced to interact in an institutional framework has cleared the path for a common European political culture. In describing key aspects of democratic systems, Schmitter and Karl suggest, in “What Democracy is…and is Not”, that “they [contingent consent and bounded uncertainty] can emerge from the interaction between antagonistic and mutually suspicious actors and that the far more benevolent and ingrained norms of civic culture are better thought of as a product and not a producer of democracy.” (252 in O'Neil and Rogowski) Judt suggests that a similar transitional process has been underway in
All of this seems to suggest that, although the European Union has encountered yet another political impasse in the forces opposed to the Lisbon Treaty, the institutional essence of the EU will not allow the present federation, now underpinned by a common currency and a host of normative standards in business and politics, to disintegrate significantly.
Thursday, October 16, 2008
No "True," but Liberal and Lasting Democracy?
Democracy and America
Schmitter and Karl are quick to argue that elections, though a distinctive part of the democratic process, are not as essential to a properly functioning democracy as one would think. While dismissing the idea of electoralism, Schmitter and Karl instead argue that civil society can be the most vital part to a developed, modern democracy. Adherence to interest associations can be seen even in the current Democrats vs. Republicans election. Instead of these interest groups working independently of these political parties, lobbyists and the like work within the plurality system and support the success of one party over another in order to further their own interests. According to Schmitter and Karl, then, the oft-feared behind-the-scenes maneuvering of interest groups is a sign of a healthy democracy in which citizens are expressing their preferences.
The authors, in the last section of their article, also argue against an assumption that many Americans believe to be true. The idea that democracies are automatically “the best” at everything they do, especially on the economic front, comes into question with the contemporary exponential economic growth of the still-authoritarian
The Land of the Free...?
Wednesday, October 15, 2008
Do We Really Want Democracy?
But are we right in jumping to the conclusion that democracy is right for everyone? Is it true that democracy is, in fact, the best form of government?
There is good reason to believe that we are not and that democracy may not be the best type of government for every country.
Democracy, like any other type of government, does not come without flaws. There has developed a tendency to pile up numerous expectations on the democratic form of government, many of which are not always met. Schmitter and Karl’s article “What Democracy Is…And Is Not” mentions these prospects for democracies that are not always fulfilled. These include the fact that democracies are not always more economically efficient than other forms of government. It is simply not feasible for people to expect new democracies to immediately be much more economically efficient than their previous form of government. Not only may democracies be less economically efficient, but also with regards to the administrative efficiency and implementation of policies. Democracies may very well prove to be slower and less efficient than other forms of government when making decisions, because more people must be included in decision-making, meaning more compromises must be made which may in turn lead to increased dissatisfaction with the outcome. In addition, democracies may not be more orderly or stable than the governments they take the place of because there will be more disagreement among officials.
Bearing these ideas in mind, should we still push for the democratization of countries who have not yet done so? Democracy is the messiest of all regimes and, since it may not bring a more effective or efficient government, may not improve the economy, and undoubtedly will not please everyone, is it really worth trying for every country?
Many people praise democracy for its ability to bring about peace and social justice and freedoms, but is it really democracy that does this?
People today bolster the idea of democracy in believing that a democratic system entails a protection of basic liberties, rule of law, separation of powers, etc. Yet just because these ideas are associated with democracy, does not mean that they are actually a part of what it means to be a democracy. In fact, as Fareed Zakaria argues, these freedoms are “theoretically different and historically distinct from democracy.” People need to stop making the mistake of believing that if a country becomes a democracy, all of its citizens will enjoy the social, political, economic and religious rights and freedoms that we associate with the United States government. Democracy itself is separate from constitutional liberalism. Because western governments have both democracy and constitutional liberalism in their systems, people incorrectly assume that the two automatically come as a pair, or that both are embodied in the term “democracy.” Democracy may not bring about constitutional liberalism, and while I applaud people for wanting those types of freedoms that come with constitutional liberalism, it is simply not correct and not realistic to think that they will appear in all countries that attempt to become democratic. People need to hesitate before jumping to the conclusion that democracy is the cure-all for any country with an unstable government, because it may not transform the country into the highly idealized form of government that people hope for it to be.
"Gray Zone" Democracies Are Not True Democracies
Carothers’ argument can be substantiated by the definitions given in “What a Democracy Is… and Is Not” by Schmitter and Karl. They would agree that these gray zone “democracies” that are supposedly transitioning are not in fact democratic just because they hold elections and give the appearance of democracy, because these governments lack many of the elements that are central to the definition of democracy. These types of governments probably even seem stable, but Schmitter and Karl explicitly identify stability as a quality that is not necessary, and might even be unnatural, to a democratic system.
Although feckless pluralist systems “have significant amounts of political freedom, regular elections, and alternation of power between genuinely different political groupings,” the government itself is corrupt and does not have effective representatives (Carothers). The civil society is weak and therefore does not influence politics to provide interest aggregation and representation of the wills of the people. One of the characteristics that Schmitter and Karl assert is necessary to democracy is the ability for change to occur. Although in a feckless plurality groups switch in and out of power with frequency, they either block the other party from making change or they do not bring about true change at all.
If a feckless pluralist system is not a true democracy, then a dominant-power system definitely does not fall into this category either. Schmitter and Karl identify free and fair elections in which practically all are allowed to vote as a necessary characteristic of a democracy. In a power-dominant system, the elections are manipulated enough so that the dominant group may remain in power, which in turn makes change virtually impossible, violating another of Schmitter and Karl’s defining characteristics of democracy. Furthermore, by prohibiting other groups to come to power, they are not engaging in cooperation and accepting the true results of elections, which is a necessary component to the feasibility of a true democratic system.